There are a number of religious arguments typically raised against ARTs. Some Christian traditions claim that all ARTs are ethically impermissible because they separate the natural process of procreation from intercourse within marriage, which is seen as unnatural (for discussion, see Cahill and McCormick, 1987; Fisher, 1989). ARTs are also viewed as a threat to the concept of the family and to the dignity of human beings, particularly inasmuch as technology dominates the origin of the human being. Thus many of these critics argue both that reproduction should not be interfered with (e.g., by using contraception) and that technology should not be used to intervene in or to help to achieve reproduction. Other traditions emphasize the unnaturalness of ARTs. Some Confucian commentators claim that any nonconjugal reproduction weakens the blood ties between family members and leads to moral and social instability (Qiu, 2002). Aside from those writing from a particular religious perspective, there are other critics who do not oppose (married heterosexual) couples making autonomous decisions about reproduction such as using contraception, but who do not view ARTs or other unnatural arrangements as morally permissible (e.g., Marquis, 1989). Still others consider ARTs in relation to environmental ethics, arguing that infertile couples should adopt since the world is already overpopulated and that the desire to have a biologically related child is selfish (for a related argument, see McKibben, 1998). According to this reasoning, individual desires to have children should give way to broader concerns about population health and control. Further ethical issues are raised by the selection criteria that are used to determine who receives ARTs. In many countries and clinics, these technologies are only made available for married heterosexual couples. Access to ARTs by unmarried (or de facto) couples and lesbian or single women is much more restricted, the latter being considered an instance of social rather than medical infertility. There have also been concerns about postmenopausal women using ARTs and donor eggs to conceive, and many clinics have rules limiting the provision of ARTs to women over a particular age (typically early to mid-forties) in part out of concerns for the welfare of the future child and relatively low success rates (Hope et al., 1995). Finally, particularly in public health-care systems where ARTs are freely available, screening criteria such as age are used to choose the best candidates (those with most likelihood of success) due to limited resources, notably donor sperm, or limits are placed on the number of cycles that can be undergone to attempt to achieve a pregnancy. In some jurisdictions (e.g., most states in the United States), there is no requirement that insurance companies provide coverage for infertility treatments, which means that only the most affluent can afford to use ARTs. Where public funds are directed at research or treatment using ARTs, there are economic concerns about whether it is just to use considerable health resources to help a relatively small number of people conceive in what are typically overstretched public health-care systems. Some argue that resources might be better utilized for research into and prevention of the various causes of infertility and related population-based problems including environmental issues, rather than individualized clinical solutions. Further, there is considerable disquiet about support for ARTs in populations where evidence shows they are unlikely to be successful, for example older women. Feminist scholars have expressed concerns about ARTs placing additional psychological, economic, and physical pressures on women to produce biologically related children (Sherwin, 1992; Donchin, 1996). They cite the problematic case of using ARTs to treat primary male infertility. This requires women to undergo onerous fertility treatments involving hyperstimulation of the ovaries and a series of surgical procedures despite the women themselves not being infertile. Further, they argue that infertility itself is a socially defined and interpreted category, rather than a natural disease category (Sherwin, 1992) and one that has been reinforced by a largely male-dominated medical profession. Most of these commentators do not deny that many women wish to have biologically related children, but they emphasize that the social and economic pressures associated with ARTs often are ignored. Others argue that ARTs have not been sufficiently well assessed, particularly with regard to their potential long-term negative effects on women’s health, especially due to the side effects of hyperstimulation (de Melo-Martin, 1998).